Of Particular Significance

Tag: naturalness

In the last post, I showed you how a projectile in a superposition of moving to the left or of moving to the right can only be measured to be doing one or the other. But what happens to the wave function of the system when the measurement is made? Does it… does it… COLLAPSE!?

Sounds scary. But it is only scary when it is badly explained.

Today I’ll show you what wave function collapse would mean, what it would require, and what a couple of the alternatives are. Among other things, I’ll show you that:

  • The standard way of explaining wave function collapse, which argues collapse is required to avoid a logical problem, is not legitimate;
  • If the Schrödinger wave equation is correct, then wave function collapse can never happen (and anything resembling “collapse” is viewed not as a physical effect but as a user’s choice);
  • Therefore, if wave function collapse really does occur, then the Schrödinger equation is wrong;
  • But if the Schrödinger wave equation is correct, an understanding of why quantum theory predicts only probabilities for multiple possibilities, rather than definite outcomes, is still lacking.

Today’s post uses several previous posts and their figures as a foundation, so I’ll start with a review of the most recent one, with links to others of relevance.

(more…)
Picture of POSTED BY Matt Strassler

POSTED BY Matt Strassler

ON March 10, 2025

So far, in the context of 1920s quantum physics, I’ve given you a sense for what an ultra-microscopic measurement consists of, and how one can make a permanent record of it. [Modern (post-1950s) quantum field theory has a somewhat different picture; please keep that in mind. We’ll get to it later.] Along the way I’ve kept the object being measured very simple: just an incoming projectile with a fairly definite motion and moderately definite position, moving steadily in one direction. But now it’s time to consider objects in more interesting quantum situations, and what it means to measure them.

The question for today is: what is a quantum superposition?

I will show you that a quantum superposition of two possibilities, in which the wave function of a system contains one possibility AND another at the same time, does not mean that both possibilities occur; it means that one OR the other may occur.

(more…)
Picture of POSTED BY Matt Strassler

POSTED BY Matt Strassler

ON March 6, 2025

As part of my post last week about measurement and measurement devices, I provided a very simple example of a measuring device. It consists of a ball sitting in a dip on a hill (Fig. 1a), or, as a microscopic version of the same, a microsopic ball, made out of only a small number of atoms, in a magnetic trap (Fig. 1b). Either object, if struck hard by an incoming projectile, can escape and never return, and so the absence of the ball from the dip (or trap) serves to confirm that a projectile has come by. The measurement is crude — it only tells us whether there was a projectile or not — but it is reasonably definitive.

Fig. 1a: A ball in a dimple on the side of the hill will be easily and permanently removed from its perch if struck by a passing object.
Fig. 1b: Similarly to Fig. 1a, a microscopic ball in a trap made from electric and/or magnetic field may easily escape the trap if struck.

In fact, we could learn more about the projectile with a bit more work. If we measured the ball’s position and speed (approximately, to the degree allowed by the quantum uncertainty principle), we would get an estimate of the energy carried by the projectile and the time when the collision occurred. But how definitive would these measurements be?

With a macroscopic ball, we’d be pretty safe in drawing conclusions. However, if the objects being measured and the measurement device are ultra-microscopic — something approaching atomic size or even smaller — then the measurement evidence is fragile. Our efforts to learn something from the microscopic ball will be in vain if the ball suffers additional collisions before we get to study it. Indeed, if a tiny ball interacts with any other object, microscopic or macroscopic, there is a risk that the detailed information about its collision with the projectile will be lost, long before we are able to obtain it.

(more…)
Picture of POSTED BY Matt Strassler

POSTED BY Matt Strassler

ON March 3, 2025

Nature could be said to be constructed out an immense number of physical processes… indeed, that’s almost the definition of “physics”. But what makes a physical process a measurement? And once we understand that, what makes a measurement in quantum physics, a fraught topic, different from measurements that we typically perform as teenagers in a grade school science class?

We could have a long debate about this. But for now I prefer to just give examples that illustrate some key features of measurements, and to focus attention on perhaps the simplest intuitive measurement device… one that we’ll explore further and put to use in many interesting examples of quantum physics.

(more…)
Picture of POSTED BY Matt Strassler

POSTED BY Matt Strassler

ON February 27, 2025

In my last post, I looked at how 1920’s quantum physics (“Quantum Mechanics”, or QM) conceives of a particle with definite momentum and completely uncertain position. I also began the process of exploring how Quantum Field Theory (QFT) views the same object. I’m going to assume you’ve read that post, though I’ll quickly review some of its main points.

In that post, I invented a simple type of particle called a Bohron that moves around in a physical space in the shape of a one-dimensional line, the x-axis.

  • I discussed the wave function in QM corresponding to a Bohron of definite momentum P1, and depicted that function Ψ(x1) (where x1 is the Bohron’s position) in last post’s Fig. 3.
  • In QFT, on the other hand, the Bohron is a ripple in the Bohron field, which is a function B(x) that gives a real number for each point x in physical space. That function has the form shown in last post’s Fig. 4.

We then looked at the broad implications of these differences between QM and QFT. But one thing is glaringly missing: we haven’t yet discussed the wave function in QFT for a Bohron of definite momentum P1. That’s what we’ll do today.

(more…)
Picture of POSTED BY Matt Strassler

POSTED BY Matt Strassler

ON February 25, 2025

Why do I find the word particle so problematic that I keep harping on it, to the point that some may reasonably view me as obsessed with the issue? It has to do with the profound difference between the way an electron is viewed in 1920s quantum physics (“Quantum Mechanics”, or QM for short) as opposed to 1950s relativistic Quantum Field Theory (abbreviated as QFT). [The word “relativistic” means “incorporating Einstein’s special theory of relativity of 1905”.] My goal this week is to explain carefully this difference.

The overarching point:

I’ve discussed this to some degree already in my article about how the view of an electron has changed over time, but here I’m going to give you a fuller picture. To complete the story will take two or three posts, but today’s post will already convey one of the most important points.

(more…)
Picture of POSTED BY Matt Strassler

POSTED BY Matt Strassler

ON February 24, 2025

Search

Buy The Book

Reading My Book?

Got a question? Ask it here.

Media Inquiries

For media inquiries, click here.